In
this excerpt from The Realm of Rhetoric from The Rhetorical
Tradition on pages 1379-1383, Perelman gives a brief history of rhetoric and explains the realm of rhetoric.
He
begins by discussing ancient philosophy and rhetoric, and uses the sophists to
give a voice to a version of rhetoric that is greater than philosophy, can
argue on both sides of the question, and puts specific opinions over general
truths. Then philosophy is given a voice by Plato, who makes philosophy greater
than rhetoric, makes rhetoric as a means to truth, and shows that when a
philosopher has perceived truth, he or she uses rhetoric to make it known.
But
for Perelman, Aristotle’s views are more nuanced, since he believed that philosophy
and rhetoric are both important, useful, and necessary. For example, a rigorous
mathematical proof would not be appropriate in a speech, and a speech would not
be appropriate in a mathematical proof. Certain situations require certain ways
of demonstration.
But
while anciently rhetoric had been taught as consisting of the five canons of
invention, arrangement, style, memory, and delivery, later in the early modern
period, Peter Ramus reduced rhetoric to style and ornamentation, and Descartes
went even further to eliminate rhetoric from philosophy altogether. Descartes
wanted a philosophy that was pure and unambiguous and, neglecting Aristotle’s
advice, also wanted to have mathematical rigor in language, in all fields, and in
all realms and areas of study. Descartes wanted to build all knowledge on what
was self-evident.
But
Perelman has a problem with self-evidence. He says that self-evidence imposes
itself on everyone and takes away people’s free will. If a thing is
self-evident, then nobody can choose to disagree with it. And even if a thing is self-evident, that self-evidence vanishes
as soon as people try to communicate it because language is fallible and not self-evident. In other words, even
the trope of “self-evidence” becomes problematic because too many deceptions
can come from it. Our words never force anyone else to believe what we
say—others have that choice whether to accept our statements or reject them.
The choices we make in language and expression, however, are “influenced by
reasons which come from dialectic and rhetoric” (1382).
Hence
Perelman writes,
“Even today the teaching of the sciences is inspired by the Cartesian approach. In the areas which are free from controversy, it is not customary to refer to the opinion of one or another scholar. The theses which are taught are considered true, or are accepted as hypotheses; but there is hardly any need to justify them.
“Thus, although axioms in the mathematical sciences, considered at first self-evident, were subsequently shown to be conventions of language, this change of perspective, however fundamental, has not affected the way in which such formal systems are laid out. In fact, if it is not a question of self-evidence, but of hypotheses or conventions, why choose this hypothesis or that convention rather than another? Most mathematicians consider such questions foreign to their discipline” (1381).
In
other words, we confess that scientific thought is human thought. And that “Every
new idea must be supported by arguments which are relevant to its discipline’s
proper methodology and which are evaluated in terms of it” (1382). So, as human
beings, we can’t get away from argumentation. Hence, rhetoric as a theory of
argumentation is the way to go. We persuade one another to viewpoints, and we
use good reasons to support our conclusions.
Philosophy
is about separating “the important from the secondary, the essential from the
accidental, the construct from the given, all from a perspective whose
pertinence and superiority does not compel everyone. Hence the obligation to
support the chosen perspective through argumentation, using analogies and
metaphors, by which the adequacy and superiority of the one perspective over
rival perspectives can be shown.” In other words, people have freedom to
choose. A theory of argumentation lets people have freedom because it does not
compel anyone to believe a certain way. A “general theory of argumentation” is
“a new rhetoric” (1383).
So
what is the realm of rhetoric? For Perelman, the realm of rhetoric includes
anything that is human: “In identifying this rhetoric with the general theory
of persuasive discourse, which seeks to gain both the intellectual and the
emotional adherence of any sort of audience, we affirm that every discourse
which does not claim an impersonal validity belongs to rhetoric” (1383). Or,
put another way, “As soon as a communication tries to influence one or more
persons, to orient their thinking, to excite or calm their emotions, to guide
their actions, it belongs to the realm of rhetoric” (1383).
No comments:
Post a Comment